Team Reasoning and Aggregate Agents
This recording is also available on stream (no ads; search enabled). Or you can view just the slides (no audio or video).
If the video isn’t working you could also watch it on youtube. Or you can view just the slides (no audio or video).
If the slides are not working, or you prefer them full screen, please try this link.
Notes
Prerequisites
This section depends on you having studied some sections from a previous lecture:
Question Session 05 (introduces the notion of an aggregate subject and Pettit (2014)’s idea about self-represention could bring them into existence)
What Are Preferences? (to have preferences, your choices must satisfy axioms including transitivity, completeness and independence. If your choices do not satisfy the axioms, this does not mean that your preferences are irrational or defective: it means that you do not have preferences at all.)
A Clarification
Why do aggregate subjects that are a consequence of team reasoning neither require the kind of self-reflection that Pettit (2014)’s idea involves nor presuppose shared agency? It is because
Sugden’s ‘account of team agency does not require that the individuals who participate in it agree to do so, or openly express their willingness to do so. What is required instead is that there is confidence among the members of the team that each of them will engage in team-directed reasoning with respect to a common set of team preferences.’ (Sugden, 2000, p. 196)
A Qualification
Sugden himself would disagree with the view about what preferences are that is assumed in this section. (This view about preferences was introduced in What Are Preferences?). Sugden rejects that view on the grounds that:
‘On some revealed-preference accounts, preference is nothing more than a disposition that a person may come to have, for whatever reason or for none, which prompts her to choose actions of one kind rather than actions of another. However, such an interpretation of preference seems not to acknowledge the sense in which the theory of rational choice is a theory of reasoning.[1] It would be more faithful to the practice of rational choice theory to say that a person's preferences are whatever she takes to be choice-relevant reasons, all things considered.’ (Sugden, 2000, p. 197)
This requires that we, as researchers, have a shared understanding of preference as ‘taking something to be a choice relevant reason’ and that this understanding is not anchored by decision theory.
Ask a Question
Your question will normally be answered in the question session of the next lecture.
More information about asking questions.
Glossary
References
Endnotes
Is decision theory (‘the theory of rational choice’) a theory of reasoning? Arguably it is a model which can be applied to various projects including understanding processes that might be called reasoning (see Are Objections to Decision Theory also Objections to the Dual Process Theory of Action?) as well as to things that are probably not reasoning (for example, motor control; see Trommershäuser, Maloney, & Landy, 2009). As reflection on these applications shows, to say that preference is a construct of decision theory does not imply that ‘preference is nothing more than a disposition ... to choose actions’. ↩︎